resolutionmini
 
Biographies de neurologues
 
Nouvelle Iconographie de La Salpêtrière
 
 L'histoire des neurosciences à La Pitié et à La Salpêtrière J Poirier
The history of neurosciences at La Pitié and La Salpêtrière J Poirier 
 
 
 

mise à jour du
8 janvier 2011
Les thèses en latin
De perspiratione insensibili
Joannes de Gorter
1689-1762
editio secunda italica 1755
 
Medicina Hippocratica
J de Gorter 1742

logo

johannes de gorter
 
Joannes de Gorter nait le 19 février 1689 en Frise Orientale à Enckuysen (Hollande). Il part étudier la médecine à Leyden sous la direction de Govard Bidloo (1649-1713), Frederik Dekker (1648-1720) et surtout de Herman Boerhaave (1668-1738) en compagnie de Bernhard Albinus (1697-1770). Après avoir soutenu sa thèse en 1712, il retrourne exercer dans sa ville natale jusqu'en 1725, époque où l'Université de Harderwijk lui offre la chaire devenue vacante après le décès de Barthélemy de Moor. Il y enseigne pendant 29 ans. L'éclat de sa renommée le fait appeler par Elisabeth, impératrice de Russie qui lui confère le titre de premier médecin de la cour. Il quitte St Pétersburg après 4 ans, en 1758, suite au décès de son épouse. Il meurt le 11 septembre 1762 en Hollande.
 
de perspiratione insensibili
 
En 1901 dans sa thèse René Trautmann écrit :
 
Gorter, en 1736, dans son livre De perspiratione insensibili parle longuement du bâillement; il lui donne pour cause un besoin de circulation plus rapide du sang et une anémie de l'encéphale: «Qua actione sanguis in venis, per musculos currentibus, magis urgetur versus venas; inde ad cor hoc tempore major sanguinis copia ducitur, atque ita deinceps, copiosor derivatio sanguinis ad cerebrum cerebellumque pro spirituum secretione. In quibus hominibus tardior sanguinis versus cerebrum fluxus, frequens solit fieri oscitatio et pandiculatio, uti in somnolentia, otio, et initio vigiliarum ad discutiendurn somnum
 
Plus loin, il classe les bâillements en bons et mauvais, selon les circonstances dans lesquelles ils se produisent: «Quod oscitatio et pandiculatio in evigilantibus bonum signum, in principio febris aliisque rnorbis malum signum, observetur, attentionem meretur. ln animalibus evigilantibus oscitationemet pandiculationem rustici inter perfectae sanitatis signa ponunt, ex quorum absentia existimant quadrupedes aegrotare. Verum multi morbis curn pandicu atione et oscitatione paroxysmum incohant: lipothymia, aliique morbi ex tardiore circulatione nati, cum his definunt. Quae, causae bonae sunt circulationem retardantes, uti somnus naturalis, his bonum signum praebent oscitationes et pandiculationes; quae vero causae malae sunt, ut est tardior circulatio in initio paroxymi febrilis et convulsionis, vel in vigiliis, oscitatio frequens, quando non expedit tardam esse circulationem. idem hoc phaenomenon malum portendit signum».
 
Bien qu'il admette la production du bâillement comme moyen de venir en aide à la circulation entravée, Gorter pense cependant qu'il arrive lorsque les «humores» sont accumulées dans l'organisme; peut-être aussi est-ce, pour lui, de cette accumulation que résulte une circulation défectueuse. Quoi qu'il en soit, dans ses commentaires d'Hippocrate, il dit pour expliquer l'aphorisme LVI du livre VII : Anxieatem... oscitationem vinum, par pari aqua potum solvit morbum: «0scitatio fit dum homo instigatur ut valide et lente aperiat os, hauriatque aerem copiosiorem pulmonibus, utactione ea, lentius moti humores constrictione musculorum os aperientium, atque majore pulmoni dilatatione per rnusculos motus animalis propellantur, quod in lethargicis somnolentis, principio febrium et ventriculi impletione est frequens; qui etiam evigilant, hac actione oscitendi propellunt lente a somno progredientes humores.»
 
Puis il explique ainsi la conclusion du maitre : «Si stagnantes in ventrioculo humores in spontaneam faciant, hujusmodi oscitationes egregie minuuntur tali poto vino diluto, quo simul ventriculi motus blande instigatur; sed inde non sequitur omnemoscilationes hac potione curari».
 
 
 De perspiratione insensibili
 De perspiratione insensibili
 
DE GORTER AND THE CLASSIFICATION OF DISEASE
The medical enlightenment of the eighteenth century
A. Cunningham & R French
Cambridge University Press 1990; p 99-102.
 
First I want to look at a figure who is less well known and who also came to construct a kind of nosology. This is Johannes de Gorter, the ordinary professor of medicine at Harderwijk. His inaugural oration, given in June 1726, is an attempt to overcome what he sees as the neglect of medical practice. Disappointed that the theoretical medicine of the schools, so subject to hypothesis and novelty, had not properly prepared him for practice, he here advocates a better system, based on arranging and indexing medical aphorisms for ready use in practice. De Gorter compares the state of practical medicine as a discipline unfavourably with that of botany, and proceeds to improve the former by means of the latter; that is, he adopts an ideal of botanical classification in arranging his aphorisms. Aphorisms, terse and irrefutable, will make the practice of medicine, he says, certain and stable, just as the characteristics of plants have been used in botany. Classification by general classes and species allows the botanist to identify plants quickly by their taxonomic characteristics, and to fit newly discovered species into the framework: so should the physician readily be able to recognise the disease from the features of the aphorism, and to fit new aphorisms, derived from experience, into their proper place, that is, where they are related to their neighbours in the classification.
 
The first step in the proposed system was to be to write down all aphorisms that dealt with cause, effects, symptoms, predictions or method of cure. This would compose a 'nursery' or sylva (the model is no doubt Bacon's) in which each 'plant' is set down with no preconceived hypothesis, but as observed. Each of them is then numbered for easy reference. Then by means of an index, related aphorisms could be grouped into genera. Finally tables were to be constructed listing the classes and species within the genera. The purpose was to construct a cumulative body of information: the operator of the system was advised to underline in each observation, or aphorism, all important words, which were to go into the index. This was so arranged that additions could be made in alphabetical order. As the system grew so the coverage became more comprehensive: a genus (in the first table) might be for example 'pain', which was to have six classes - location, type, causes, symptoms, methods of cure and change. Class one might be 'chest', which then in table two breaks down into species, like ribpain or clavicle-pain.
 
We can learn a little more from de Gorter about eighteenth-century attempts to classify disease. As we see in Martin's chapter on Sauvages in this volume, some inspiration for the attempts came from Bacon, and more from the botanists. Five years or so before Sauvages was classifying diseases on the model of the botanist Joseph Pitton de Tournefort, de Gorter was using a botanical method that brought him into contact with Linnaeus, at whose graduation (in 1735) in Harderwijk de Gorter acted as sponsor; at that time de Gorter's son David joined Linnaeus on botanising expeditions.
 
Twenty-four years after his inaugural dissertation de Gorter was ready to put his observations and reading to the test of his system. But it had changed in the interval. It was no longer a classification of aphorisms. Perhaps they have served their purpose and have turned this System of Medical Practice into a kind of nosology of disease. Half of it is concerned with general diseases after the Boerhaavian model and the other half is particular diseases, where the numbered paragraphs approximate to species of disease and seem to be derived from the original numbered aphorisms. The basis of classification is function or location; groups of diseases are 'titles', not classes. His modest hope is to open a little window to the true names of diseases', and the cross-referencing by which this is achieved also enables the reader to discover from the listed symptoms and locations a suitable remedy, even if he does not know the name of the disease.
 
In short de Gorter has used a botanical technique not so much to classify disease entities in the way that Sauvages was to do, but to refine and make more practical the picture of disease as disordered function. There is one particular in which, during the course of his life, he departed from the strict Boerhaavian model, as others also did. In 1730, four years after his inaugural oration he gave another, on the soul in medicine. Unlike Boerhaave and Hoffmann, de Gorter said that the soul has 'automatic or vital' motions in the body, such as that of the heart and intestines; or it can at least affect such motions. His devotion to medical practice, the subject of most of his writing, later convinced him that there were hidden things in the body that could not be explained on the basis of chemistry, mechanics or hydraulics, but which come from 'distinct laws of life'. He first formulated what he called General Laws and had his son David defend them in a thesis in 1731, and later discovered Special Laws. By reason of these he was obliged to withdraw from the usual mechanical explanation, qua recedo a consueta explicatione Mechanica. The critical case was secretion, where the particles and pores of the mechanists had replaced the old faculties. But to de Gorter secretion was essentially a vital motion, following laws that were not found in non-living systems. There had to be, he concluded, an active principle in the body. Certainly, he said, such things had not been admitted in discussion until now, but this was because the chemists and physicists had succeeded in closing the door and holding up the progress of knowledge.
 
This was a personal conversion for de Gorter, a reaction against the campaign for mechanism typified if not started by Boerhaave's oration on the topic. Similar reactions were recorded by Whytt in Edinburgh, Sauvages in Montpellier and Rosetti in Padua, in the 1730S and 1740s. Rosetti indeed presents himself as part of a campaign to reintroduce the Hippocratic principle of movement, the enormon. This term was also used by Gaub, whose system of animistic pathology was partly adopted by Whytt in lecturing on pathology in Edinburgh in the 1760s. The choice of the term seems a deliberate one by animists in their campaign against mechanism. What was common to the animist alternative was that the lower soul(s) of seventeenth-century doctrines was abandoned. Where the passivity of the animal machine made an energetic soul a necessary part of theory, to identify that soul (as the animists did) with the immortal soul of Christian doctrine drew medicine and religion together in a satisfactory way. Rosetti identified the Hippocratic enormon or impetum faciens with the divine breath breathed into the body of man. It was for religious rather than physiological reasons that the soul was held to be perfect: it is not damaged by disease, said de Gorter, and any apparent vices - the subject matter of pathology - came from the body. Gaub and Whytt both claimed that even in cases of drunkenness it is the body that is affected, not the soul. Likewise in therapeutics, medicines act on the body, not on the soul. Where practice renders complex motions habitual and almost unconscious, it is the body, said de Gorter, not the soul, that becomes used to the actions. In all this the way in which the body and soul interact remains unknown, and is attributed directly to God.
 
A characteristic of eighteenth-century animism in the period after Stahl was that the soul was generally thought to be super-added to a mechanical body. It was a rigorous use of mathematics to prove that the machine of the body could not produce its own motion that convinced Sauvages and Whytt that there must be an additional, nonmaterial source of movement. In contrast the mechanists' arguments were generally qualitative, not mathematical. They were statements of faith in a principle, a faith that de Gorter questioned. A large proportion of such arguments was concerned with circulation and the hydraulics of the various fluids and vessels. Guerrini has pointed out the importance of secretion for Cheyne, and we can recall the experiments of Stephen Hales and the equally well-known calculations of the force of the heart by Borelli, Keill and Bernouilli, together with the hydraulicism of Pitcairne and the Newtonians, to locate de Gorter's experiments. He did not deny the laws of mechanics and hydraulics, but insisted that vital motions rose above them. The proof was experimental: attach the cut (upper) end of the carotid artery of a living dog to a tube of warm water raised to the height to which the heart would send the blood, and the water, de Gorter found, comes down the tube and passes through the brain. But with a dead dog, not twice the height forces water through the brain. Nor in the dead animal can water be compelled to pass through the kidneys, the liver or the pancreas: secretion is a vital process.
 
johanes de gorter